TV Game Shows - FAQ
If any of the following conditions are true the second player should spin again.
- His score is less than the first player’s score.
- His score is 50 cents or less.
- His score is 65 cents or less and he has tied the first player.
- Player picks door 1 --> player wins
- Player picks door 2 --> player loses
- Player picks door 3 --> player loses
Following are what would happen if the player had a strategy of switching.
- Player picks door 1 --> Host reveals goat behind door 2 or 3 --> player switches to other door --> player loses
- Player picks door 2 --> Host reveals goat behind door 3 --> player switches to door 1 --> player wins
- Player picks door 3 --> Host reveals goat behind door 2 --> player switches to door 1 --> player wins
So by not switching the player has 1/3 chance of winning. By switching the player has a 2/3 chance of winning. So the player should definitely switch.
For further reading on the Monty Hall paradox, I recommend the article at Wikipedia.
- $0.50
- $1
- $2
- $5
- $10
- $25
- $50
- $75
- $100
- $150
- $250
- $500
- $750
- $1,000
- $1,500
- $2,000
- $3,000
- $5,000
- $7,500
- $10,000
- $15,000
- $30,000
- $50,000
- $75,000
- $100,000
- $200,000
The contestant selects one of the briefcases to be THEIR suitcase. Through a process of elimination, by opening the other suitcases, they try and work out how much money is their case, or whether it would be wiser to take a "Bank offer". The Bank Offers are based on, but not equivalent to, the arithmetic mean of the remaining briefcases. So, if there are mainly large valued briefcases remaining, there is a high chance that the contestant’s briefcase is valuable, and so the Bank Offer will be generous. Conversely, if the player has been less fortunate and opened the more valuable briefcases, then the Bank Offer will be low. What would be the best strategy to employ if you were a contestant on this game? A non-mathematical gut instinct strategy would be ignore the Bank offers and carry on opening cases until either the $200,000 was opened and eliminated, or both the $100,000 and $75,000 were opened and eliminated. What’s the math behind this game, Wizard?
- 0.01
- 1
- 5
- 10
- 25
- 50
- 75
- 100
- 200
- 300
- 400
- 500
- 750
- 1000
- 5000
- 10000
- 25000
- 50000
- 75000
- 100000
- 200000
- 300000
- 400000
- 500000
- 750000
- 1000000
Here is the flow of the game:
- Player picks one case for himself
- Player opens up six of the remaining 25 cases.
- Banker makes an offer.
- If player declines he opens five more of the 19 remaining cases.
- Banker makes an offer.
- If player declines he opens four more of the 14 remaining cases.
- Banker makes an offer.
- If player declines he opens three more of the 10 remaining cases.
- Banker makes an offer.
- If player declines he opens two more of the 7 remaining cases.
- Banker makes an offer.
- If player declines he opens one more of the remaining cases.
- Keep repeating steps 11 and 12 until player accepts an offer or player has the last unopened case.
The following chart plots the player’s expected value and the banker’s offer.

The most obvious thing to be learned from these three charts are that the first four to six bank offers are terrible deals. The average suitcase has $131,477.54 before any are opened. To only offer $9000 to $13000 the first stage is a deal only a fool would make. However gradually the offers get better. Game 2 shows us the expected values were almost the same as the banker offers towards the end of the game when the player’s expected value was fairly low. However in games 1 and 3 when the expected values were higher the banker apparently was trying to take advantage of the risk averse nature of most people when large amounts are involved. I don’t know if it mattered but the contestant in game 2 appeared to be a gambler who wanted to win big. Based on comments by the host, who communicates to the banker by phone, the banker does appear to take the contestants words and actions into consideration. If I were in the banker’s shoes I would act much the same.
If the player is neither risk averse nor risk prone, and also ignoring tax implications, the player should keep refusing banker offers until one exceeds the average of the remaining suitcases. For most people the progressive nature of the income tax code favors taking a deal. As I have said before I would roughly say the value of money is proportional to the log of the amount. So the more wealth you have going into the game the more inclined you should be to gamble and refuse the banker offers. With such large amounts involved, no strategy will fit everybody. However I can fairly confidently say that the player should refuse the first four to six offers and then take the offers on a case by case basis (pun intended).
Links:
You can watch Deal or No Deal at NBC.com.
Archive of past shows.
Let me explain what happened on Let’s Make a Deal. The contestant would choose one of three curtains. One would contain a very valuable prize and the other two smaller prizes. For the sake of argument let’s say behind one curtain was a car and behind the other two a goat. Then Monty would always, I repeat ALWAYS, open up one of the two unchosen curtains to reveal a goat. After hundreds of shows this would imply that Monty Hall (the host) knew where the car was and deliberately opened a curtain that revealed a goat. Obviously when the player chose his curtain the probability it held the car was 1/3 and the probability one of the two unchosen curtains held the car was 2/3. Monty is then predestined to open an unchosen curtain containing a goal. Predestined is the key word here. Because Monty can not open the player’s curtain at this stage the probability of the player’s curtain reveals the car stays at 1/3. The probability an unchosen curtain reveales the car remains at 2/3, however it is now all on one curtain. So after a goat is revelead the probability the player’s curtain has the car is 1/3 and the probability the other unopened curtain has the car is 2/3, making switching a wise choise.
The following table shows all the possible outcomes. In the case where the player chose the curtain with the car I had Monty opening a curtain arbitrarily. You can see that not switching results in a 1/3 probability of winning, and switching results in a 2/3 probability of winnning.
Let’s Make a Deal
Player Chooses |
Car | Curtain Opened |
Probability | Win by Switching |
1 | 1 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 1 | 2 | 5.56% | N |
1 | 1 | 3 | 5.56% | N |
1 | 2 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 2 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 2 | 3 | 11.11% | Y |
1 | 3 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 3 | 2 | 11.11% | Y |
1 | 3 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 1 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 1 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 1 | 3 | 11.11% | Y |
2 | 2 | 1 | 5.56% | N |
2 | 2 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 2 | 3 | 5.56% | N |
2 | 3 | 1 | 11.11% | Y |
2 | 3 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 3 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 1 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 1 | 2 | 11.11% | Y |
3 | 1 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 2 | 1 | 11.11% | Y |
3 | 2 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 2 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 3 | 1 | 5.56% | N |
3 | 3 | 2 | 5.56% | N |
3 | 3 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
Meanwhile in Deal or No Deal nothing is predestined. Let’s assume on Deal or No Deal the amounts remaining were $0.01, $1, and $1,000,000. With three cases left it IS possible that the opened case will contain the million dollars. The following table shows the possible outcomes with three cases left. Remember, the player can not open his own case.
Deal or No Deal
Player Chooses |
Million $ | Case Opened |
Probability | Win by Switching |
1 | 1 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 1 | 2 | 5.56% | N |
1 | 1 | 3 | 5.56% | N |
1 | 2 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 2 | 2 | 5.56% | Hopeless |
1 | 2 | 3 | 5.56% | Y |
1 | 3 | 1 | 0% | n/a |
1 | 3 | 2 | 5.56% | Y |
1 | 3 | 3 | 5.56% | Hopeless |
2 | 1 | 1 | 5.56% | Hopeless |
2 | 1 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 1 | 3 | 5.56% | Y |
2 | 2 | 1 | 5.56% | N |
2 | 2 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 2 | 3 | 5.56% | N |
2 | 3 | 1 | 5.56% | Y |
2 | 3 | 2 | 0% | n/a |
2 | 3 | 3 | 5.56% | Hopeless |
3 | 1 | 1 | 5.56% | Hopeless |
3 | 1 | 2 | 5.56% | Y |
3 | 1 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 2 | 1 | 5.56% | Y |
3 | 2 | 2 | 5.56% | Hopeless |
3 | 2 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
3 | 3 | 1 | 5.56% | N |
3 | 3 | 2 | 5.56% | N |
3 | 3 | 3 | 0% | n/a |
What the Deal or No Deal table shows is that with three cases left the probability the player opens the million dollar case is 1/3 (hopeless to win), the probability a switching player will win is 1/3, and the probability a switching player will lose is 1/3. Thus the odds are the same to switch cases. Once there are only two cases left the probability each case contains the larger prize is 50/50.
log(b) = 5.520696
b = 105.520696
b = $331,662.50.
So this hypothetical player should be indifferent at a bank offer of $331,662.50. The lesser your wealth going into the game the more conservatively you should play. Usually in the late stages of the game the bank offers are close to expected value, sometimes a little more bit more. The only rational case where a player could win the million is if he had a lot of wealth going into the game and/or the bank offers were unusually stingy. The producers seem to like hard-working middle class people, so we’re unlikely to see somebody who can afford to be cavalier when large amounts are involved. I have also never seen the bank make offers under 90% of expected value late in the game. The time when we will see somebody win the million is when a degenerate gambler gets on the show who can’t stop. When that happens I will be rooting for the banker.
Just my two cents, and no reply is necessary.
I can offer three theories why the banker sometimes offers more than the average of the remaining cases.
- The show tries to portray the banker as sweating the money in his office. Howie Mandel is often commenting on the banker’s mood and tone of voice. Maybe it makes the show more dramatic to think of the banker as a risk-averse bean counter, preferring to cut his losses, than risk giving out a big prize.
- The real banker truly is risk-averse. This is getting out of my area of expertise, but from my understanding, game and reality shows are usually produced by a company independent from the television network. These smaller companies will seek out an insurance company to mitigate the risk of contestants winning the larger prizes. In such a case, the insurance company would be the real banker, and may be influencing the behavior of the banker on the show. The insurance companies that insure odd-ball stuff like this are not gigantic, and may prefer playing it safe when large amounts are involved.
In your example, the banker offer was 9.92% above expected value. If the banker were following the Kelly Criterion, such an offer would have been made with a total bankroll of only $782,008, which is less than the maximum prize. No self-respecting insurance company would be that conservative. Clearly, this reason alone cannot justify the offer in your example.
- The show is trying to make the contestants look stupid and greedy. Shows like Are You Smarter than a Fifth Grader and the Tonight Show's “Jaywalking” would not be successful if we didn’t find some satisfaction in laughing at the trivia-challenged. The shows Friend or Foe and The Weakest Link were outstanding at exposing greed in human nature. I must confess a sense of schadenfreude when a contestant refuses an above expected value offer, and walks with the lower amount in his case.
I tend to think the reason is a combination of these three reasons, but mainly the third.
If I ended this answer here, I’m sure I would get comments, questioning whether the hypothetical banker offers would have really been made. The implication being that they are puffed up for dramatic effect. I have recorded the specifics of 13 games. In one of them, with three cases left ($1,000; $5,000; and $50,000), the average was $18,667, and the offer was $21,000. That is 12.5% over the expected value. In another show, with two cases left ($400 and $750,000), the average was $375,200, and the offer was $400,000. That is 6.6% above expected value. So, I see no reason to question the integrity of the hypothetical offers.
Links:
Deal or no deal formula: This page shows old, and new, formulas for calculating the banker offer, based on the free game at the Deal or No Deal web site.
Player A: $10,000
Player B: $8,000
Player C: $3,500
Let’s start with player C. He should anticipate that A might bet $6001, to stay above B if B is right. However, if A is wrong, that would lower him to $3999. C would need to bet at least $500, and be right, to beat A in such a scenario. However, in my opinion, if you must be right to win, you may as well bet big. So if I were C I would bet everything.
B is torn between betting big or small. A small bet should be $999 or less, to stay above C if C is correct. The benefit of a small bet is staying above C no matter what, hoping that A will go big, and be wrong. A big bet does not necessarily have to go the whole way, but it may as well. The benefit of a big bet is hoping that either A goes small, or goes big and is wrong, but both require B to be right.
A basically wants to go the same way as B. A small bet for A can be anything from $0 to $1000, which will stay above B if B bets $999. A big bet should be $6001, to guarantee a win if A is right, and still retain hope if B goes big, and all three players are wrong.
To help with the probabilities of the eight possible outcomes of right and wrong answers, I looked at the Final Jeopardy results for seasons 20 to 24, from j-archive.com(no longer available). Here is what the results look like, where player A is the leader, followed by player B, and C in last.
Possible Outcomes in Final Jeopardy
Player A | Player B | Player C | Probability |
Right | Right | Right | 21.09% |
Right | Right | Wrong | 9.73% |
Right | Wrong | Right | 10.27% |
Wrong | Right | Right | 8.74% |
Right | Wrong | Wrong | 13.33% |
Wrong | Right | Wrong | 10.27% |
Wrong | Wrong | Right | 8.63% |
Wrong | Wrong | Wrong | 17.92% |
Using the kind of game theory logic I explain in problem 192 at my site mathproblems.info, I find that A and B should randomize their strategy as follows.
Player A should bet big with probability 73.6% and small with probability 26.4%.
Player B should bet big with probability 67.3% and small with probability 32.7%.
Player C should bet big with probability 100.0%.
If this strategy is followed, the probability of each player’s winning will be as follows:
Player A: 66.48%
Player B: 27.27%
Player C: 6.25%
As an aside, based on the table above, the probability of the leader getting Final Jeopardy correct is 54.4%, for the second-place player, 49.8%, and 48.7% for the third-place player. The overall probability is 51.0%.
As a practical note, players do have knowledge of betting behavior. In my judgment, players tend to bet big more often than mathematically justified. Interestingly, I find wagering in Daily Double to be too conservative than mathematically justified. One of the reasons I believe Ken Jennings did so well was aggressive wagering on the Double Doubles. Anyway, in reality if I were actually on the show, I would assume the other two players would bet aggressively. So my actual wagers would be $6000 as A (being nice to B), $0 as B, and $3495 as C (leaving a little un-bet, in case A foolishly bets everything or all but $1, and is wrong).
Before somebody challenges me about how one could draw a random number in the actual venue, let me suggest the Stanford Wong strategy of using the second hand of your watch to draw a random number from 1 to 60.
The player may yell "Stop!" at any time, and he will bank the amount showing on screen. If the player does not stop in time, and the machine runs out of money, then he banks nothing. A hostess provides statistics, such as number of machines left to pick, amount left to earn, average amount needed per machine to win, and what amounts remain in the machines.
A player can "play the gaps," in that if a run of machines have been picked, say, £4k, £5k, and £6k, a machine would be guaranteed to make it to £7,000 once it passes the £3,000 mark. My question is, what kind of strategy should a player use?
The hostess conveniently tells you the average amount you need per remaining machine to reach your game. After hours of scribbling, I can’t come up with anything better than setting a stopping goal of about 25% higher than the required average. That is just an educated guess, so please don’t ask me to prove it is optimal. As you noted, also ride the gaps, never stopping just before an amount that was already picked.
When there are only two machines left, if the total amount needed is £13,000 or less, I would try to get it all in the second-to-last machine. If £14,000 or more, I would try to get half of it at the next machine.
If they should bring back this show, I hope my UK readers will let me know. This is the kind of puzzle that I could become obsessed with, like the Eternity puzzle, which was coincidentally (or not) also out of the UK.
P.S. Why do you spell "colour" with a u in the UK? It makes no sense to me.
First, let’s calculate the expected value of a prize that is not paired with a second chance. The following table shows that average is $1371.74.
Punch a Bunch Prize Distribution with no Second Chance
Prize | Number | Probability | Expected Win |
25000 | 1 | 0.021739 | 543.478261 |
10000 | 1 | 0.021739 | 217.391304 |
5000 | 3 | 0.065217 | 326.086957 |
1000 | 5 | 0.108696 | 108.695652 |
500 | 9 | 0.195652 | 97.826087 |
250 | 9 | 0.195652 | 48.913043 |
100 | 9 | 0.195652 | 19.565217 |
50 | 9 | 0.195652 | 9.782609 |
Total | 46 | 1.000000 | 1371.739130 |
Second, calculate the average prize that does have a second chance. The following table shows that average is $225.
Punch a Bunch Prize Distribution with Second Chance
Prize | Number | Probability | Expected Win |
500 | 1 | 0.250000 | 125.000000 |
250 | 1 | 0.250000 | 62.500000 |
100 | 1 | 0.250000 | 25.000000 |
50 | 1 | 0.250000 | 12.500000 |
Total | 4 | 1.000000 | 225.000000 |
Third, create an expected value table based on the number of second chances the player finds. This can be found using simple math. For example, the probability of 2 second chances is (4/50)×(3/49)×(46/48). The expected win given s second chances is $1371.74 + s×$225. The following table shows the probability and average win for 0 to 4 second chances.
Punch a Bunch Prize Return Table
Second Chances | Probability | Average Win | Expected Win |
4 | 0.000004 | 2271.739130 | 0.009864 |
3 | 0.000200 | 2046.739130 | 0.408815 |
2 | 0.004694 | 1821.739130 | 8.551020 |
1 | 0.075102 | 1596.739130 | 119.918367 |
0 | 0.920000 | 1371.739130 | 1262.000000 |
Total | 1.000000 | 1390.888067 |
So the average win per punch (including additional money from second chances) is $1390.89.
The following table shows my strategy of the minimum win to accept, according to the number of punches remaining. Note the player can get to $1,400 with prizes of $1,000 + $250, + $100 + $50 via three second chances.
Punch a Bunch Strategy
Punches Remaining | Minimum to Stand |
3 | $5,000 |
2 | $5,000 |
1 | $1,400 |
This question was raised and discussed in the forum of my companion site Wizard of Vegas.
For the benefit of other readers, let me review the rules first.
- A team of players starts with $1,000,000.
- The team is given a multiple choice question.
- The team is to divide his money among the possible answers. Whatever money is put on the correct answer will move onto the next question.
- The team must completely rule out at least one possible answer by not putting any money on it.
- This process repeats for several rounds. The player is also given one chance to change his mind.
Obviously, if the team is sure of the answer then he should put all his money on the correct answer. If the team can narrow down the answer to two, but assigns each a 50% chance of being correct, then they should divide his money equally between the two choices.
Where it gets more difficult is if the team leans towards one answer but doesn’t completely rule out one or more of the others. Let’s look at an example. Suppose the team determines the probability of each correct answer as follows: A 10%, B 20%, C 30%, D 40%. How should they divide up his money?
I claim the answer is to follow the Kelly Criterion. Briefly, the team should maximize the log of his wealth with every question. To do this, you have to consider how much wealth you already have.
Let’s say your existing wealth, which you have accumulated independently of the show, is $100,000. It is your first question, so you have $1,000,000 of game show money to split up. First eliminate the option with the lowest probability, to conform with the show rules. Then you want to maximize 0.2×log(100,000+b*1,000,000) + 0.3×log(100,000+c*1,000,000) + 0.4×log(100,000+d*1,000,000), where lower-case a, b, and c refer to the portion placed on each answer.
This could be solved with calculus and solving a trinomial equation, trial and error, or my preference, the "goal seek" feature in Excel. Whatever you use, the right answer is to put 18.9% on B, 33.3% on C, and 47.8% on D.
Of course, nobody on the show is going to be able to do all this math in the time allowed, not to mention that you also have to move a lot of bundles of cash as well in that time. My more practical advice is to just divide up the money in proportion to your assessment of the probability of the answer’s being correct, assuming the least likely choice is not a possibility. In the example, that would cause a split of 22.2% on B, 33.3% on C, and 44.4% on D.
This question was raised and discussed in the forum of my companion site Wizard of Vegas.
- Players play one at a time while players yet to play are kept off stage and are given no information about how any previous player did.
- There are 100 cards, numbered 1 to 100.
- A player starts by choosing any card.
- After looking at it, the player may keep it or switch for a new card.
- All cards are dealt with replacement. In other words, old cards are put back in the deck, including after discarding.
- The player who draws the highest card wins.
Is there any positional advantage to going last in this game? What is the optimal strategy for each player?
Here is a YouTube video showing the game.
Second, there must be a Nash Equilibrium to the game where a strategy to stand with a score of at least x points will be superior to any other strategy. The question is finding x.
What I did was ask myself what would be the strategy if instead of a card numbered 1 to 100, each player got a random number uniformly distributed between 0 and 1 and look for the point x where a perfect logician would be indifferent between standing and switching. With that answer, it is easy to apply the answer to a discrete distribution from 1 to 100.
I'll stop talking at this point and let my readers enjoy the problem. See the links below for the answer and solution.
Answer for a continuous distribution from 0 to 1.
Answer for a discrete distribution from 1 to 100.
For my solution, please click here (PDF).
This question was raised and discussed in my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
My advice is to always submit a selection that has a chance of winning, given the previous history of selections and scores. If the first score is 0, then don't reverse two sets of two tags, but instead move everything by one position in either direction.
If you're not able to do the logic on the spot, then I spell it out for you below. To use this strategy, assign the different tags the letters A, B, C, and D. Then place them in the order shown, from left to right on the stage. Always start with ABCD. Then look up the score history below and choose the sequence of tags indicated for that score sequence.
If 0, then BCDA
If 0-0, then CDAB
If 0-0-0, then DABC (must win)
If 0-1, then BDAC
If 0-1-0, then CADB (must win)
If 0-1-1, then CDBA
If 0-1-1-0, then DCAB (must win)
If 0-2, then BADC
If 0-2-0, then DCBA (must win)
If 1, then ACDB
If 1-0, then BDCA
If 1-0-0, then CABD
If 1-0-0-1, then CBAC (must win)
If 1-1, then BDCA
If 1-1-0, then CABD
If 1-1-0-1, then CBAC (must win)
If 1-1-1, then BCAD (must win)
If 2, then ABDC
If 2-0, then BACD (must win)
If 2-1, then ACBD
If 2-1-0, then DBCA
If 2-1-1, then ADCB
If 2-1-1-0, then CBAD (must win)
The following table shows the probability of each number of total turns. The bottom right cell shows an expected number of turns of 10/3.
Race Game
Turns | Combinations | Probability | Return |
---|---|---|---|
1 | 1 | 0.041667 | 0.041667 |
2 | 4 | 0.166667 | 0.333333 |
3 | 8 | 0.333333 | 1.000000 |
4 | 8 | 0.333333 | 1.333333 |
5 | 3 | 0.125000 | 0.625000 |
Total | 24 | 1.000000 | 3.333333 |
This question is discussed on my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
As a word of explanation to other readers, let me explain what you're talking about. The Showcase Showdown is a game played on the game show The Price is Right. In the Showcase Showdown, each player takes his turn spinning a wheel which has an equal probability of stopping on every amount evenly divisible by .05 from .05 to 1.00 . If the player does not like their first spin they may spin again, adding the second spin to their first, however if they go over 1.00 they are immediately disqualified. In the event of a tie, each player will get one spin in a tie-breaker round, the highest spin wins. In the event of another tie, this process will repeat until the tie is broken.
The main purpose of the Showcase Showdown is to advance to the Showcase. However, there are also immediate cash prizes too, as follows:
- In the first round, if any player get a total of $1.00, whether in one sum or the sum of two spins, he shall win $1,000.
- In the first, and only first, tie-breaker round, if the wheel lands on $0.05 or $0.15, then the player shall win $10,000.
- In the first, and only first, tie-breaker round, if the wheel lands on $1.00, then the player shall win $25,000.
I explain the optimal strategy to the Showcase Showdown in column #101. Assuming that strategy is followed, the following table answers your questions and various other.
Showcase Showdown Statistics
Question | Answer |
---|---|
Expected $1000 winners first round | 0.253790 |
Probability 2-player tie | 0.113854 |
Probability 3-player tie | 0.004787 |
Expected $10000 winners second round | 0.024207 |
Expected $25000 winners second round | 0.012104 |
Expected total prize money | $798.45 |
Probability any given player wins $1000 | 0.084597 |
Probability any given player wins $10000 | 0.008069 |
Probability any given player wins $25000 | 0.004035 |
The bottom row of the table shows that if you make the Showcase Showdown, without considering your order to spin, your chances of winning $25,000 is 0.004035, or 1 in 248.
This question is asked and discussed in my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
Let's call the former team of nine player team 1 and the one of six player team 2. The number of ways you could pick three players from team 1 and two from team 2 is combin(9,3)×combin(6,2) = 1,260. The total number of ways to pick five out of 15 players is combin(15,5) = 3,003. So, the probability the first team is split 3/2 in favor of team 1 is 1,260/3,003 = 41.96%.
If that happened, then team 1 will have six players left and team 2 four players. The number of ways you could pick three players from team 1 and two from team 2 is combin(6,3)×combin(4,2) = 120. The total number of ways to pick five out of 10 players left is combin(10,5) = 252. So, the probability the second team is split 3/2 in of favor team 1, given that the first team is already split 3/2 that way, is 120/252 = 47.62%.
If the first two new teams are split 3/2, in favor of the former team 1, then the final team will be split 3/2 among the leftovers.
Thus, the answer to your question is 41.96% × 47.62% × 100% = 19.98%.
Formulas:
combin(x,y)=x!/((y!*(x-y)!)
x! = 1*2*3*...*x
This question is raised and discussed in my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
Let me set the stage. On the June 3, 2019 James was within easy reach of breaking the record for total money won in regular games, which still stands at $2,520,700. James average win per game was much more than what he needed to break the record. So all eyes were watching on June 3 to see the record broken.
Instead, what happens is not only does James not break the record, but he loses. The winner, Emma, played a very strong strategic game as well as being good with the buzzer and simply answering correctly. She played just as James normally did. Going into Final Jeopardy the scores were:
- Emma — $26,600
- James — $23,400
- Jay — $11,000
In these situations, where second place has more than half of first place, and third place does not, it typically comes down to first and second place choosing to go high or low with their final wager. A high wager for first place is enough to lock in a win if correct. To be specific, two times the second place score less the first place score plus one dollar. That is exactly what Emma did with a wager of 2×$23,400 - $26,600 + $1 = $20,201. Most of the time, the first place player does this.
However, James didn't know what Emma would do when deciding his wager. The following table shows who would win according to what combination of wagers.
Click on image for larger version.
If Emma wagers at least $20,201 then she locks in a win if correct.
If Emma wagers low then she will win if either (a) James wagers low or (b) James wagers high and is wrong.
If James wagers high then he wins if (a) Emma goes high, Emma is wrong, and James is right, or (b) Emma goes low and James is right.
If James wagers low then he wins if Emma goes high and is wrong.
If perfect logicians were playing, both would randomize their decisions. However, rarely does the leader go low in these situations where he/she can be caught. If James anticipates Emma to go high, then he absolutely should go low. This way he doesn't have to get Final Jeopardy right to win, he just has to hope Emma blows it.
James actual bid was the correct amount to cover Jay if Jay bet everything and was right: $23,400 - 2×$11,000 - $1 = $1,399, which satisfied as a low wager for purposes of beating Emma.
If correct, James would get an extra $1,000 for coming in second, compared to third.
In conclusion, I completely reject the conspiracy theory that James threw the game. He played the right way and lost due to a combination of playing a strong competitor and what most people would call "bad luck."
External Links
- Jeopardy hall of fame
- James Holzhauer on Jeopardy — Discussion in my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
Let me get a disclaimer out of the way first. The following analysis is based on statistical averages. An actual player should make mental adjustments for how well he knows the Final Jeopardy category as well estimating the opponent's chances of getting it correct.
To answer your question, I first looked at four seasons of data from the Jeopardy Archive to see the four possible combinations of the first (leading) and second place (chasing) player getting Final Jeopardy right and wrong.
Final Jeopardy Scorecard
Leading Player | Chasing Player Correct | Chasing Player Incorrect | Total |
---|---|---|---|
Correct | 29.0% | 25.5% | 54.5% |
Incorrect | 17.7% | 27.8% | 45.5% |
Total | 46.8% | 53.2% | 100.0% |
Before going on, let's define some variables:
x = Probability leading player goes high.
y = Probability chasing player goes high.
f(x,y) = Probability of the high player winning.
Let's express f(x,y) in terms of x and y from the table above:
f(x,y) = 0.823xy + 0.545x(1-y) + 0.468(1-x)y + (1-x)(1-y)
f(x,y) = 0.810 xy - 0.455x - 0.532y + 1
To find the optimal values for x and y, let's take the derivative of f(x,y) with respect to both x and y.
f(x,y) d/dx = -0.455 + 0.810y = 0
Thus y = 0.455/0.810 = 0.562
f(x,y) d/dy = -0.532 + 0.810x = 0
Thus x = 0.523/0.810 = 0.657
So, the high player should wager high with probability 65.7% and the low player should wager high with probability 56.2%.
Based on watching, I think the high player wagers high greater than 65.7% of the time, thus if I were in second place, I would go low.
If both players following this randomizing strategy, the probability the leading player will win is 70.1%.
Putting all theory aside, if you're leading, predict what the chasing player will do and do the same. If you're chasing, predict the leading player's action and do the opposite. This strategy goes for all such tournaments.This question is raised and discussed in my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
Daily Double Location
Row | Column 1 | Column 2 | Column 3 | Column 4 | Column 5 | Column 6 | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
1 | 5 | - | 3 | 3 | 2 | 3 | 16 |
2 | 280 | 137 | 216 | 167 | 207 | 140 | 1,147 |
3 | 820 | 442 | 677 | 658 | 643 | 472 | 3,712 |
4 | 1,095 | 659 | 982 | 907 | 895 | 627 | 5,165 |
5 | 787 | 403 | 670 | 671 | 613 | 476 | 3,620 |
Total | 2,987 | 1,641 | 2,548 | 2,406 | 2,360 | 1,718 | 13,660 |
Source: J! Archive.
Here is the same data in the form of how often a Daily Double is found in each cell of the board.
Daily Double Probability
Row | Column 1 | Column 2 | Column 3 | Column 4 | Column 5 | Column 6 | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
1 | 0.0% | 0.0% | 0.0% | 0.0% | 0.0% | 0.0% | 0.1% |
2 | 2.0% | 1.0% | 1.6% | 1.2% | 1.5% | 1.0% | 8.4% |
3 | 6.0% | 3.2% | 5.0% | 4.8% | 4.7% | 3.5% | 27.2% |
4 | 8.0% | 4.8% | 7.2% | 6.6% | 6.6% | 4.6% | 37.8% |
5 | 5.8% | 3.0% | 4.9% | 4.9% | 4.5% | 3.5% | 26.5% |
Total | 21.9% | 12.0% | 18.7% | 17.6% | 17.3% | 12.6% | 100.0% |
The reason for searching for Daily Doubles is they are a good way to double your score. Most contestants will have a probability of about 80% to 90% of getting any given clue right. It is a great value to get even money on a wager you have an 80% to 90% chance of winning. A major reason James Holtzhauer won as much as he did was aggressive Daily Double searching and then going "all in" most of the time when he found them. It is also how he lost against Emma, when she employed the same strategy against him.
For the benefit of readers who aren't familiar with the game, here is a video of it.
I submit that the following strategy results in a minimum average number of turns. There are many strategies that would tie it, but I don't think any can beat it.
To use the strategy, label the four price tags as 1, 2, 3, and 4. Place them on the four prizes according to the history of how many you got right in the past, starting with the first turn on the left.
Race Game Strategy
History | Prize 1 | Prize 2 | Prize 3 | Prize 4 |
---|---|---|---|---|
None | 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 |
0 | 2 | 1 | 4 | 3 |
0,0 | 3 | 4 | 2 | 1 |
0,0,0 | 4 | 3 | 1 | 2 |
0,0,2 | 3 | 4 | 1 | 2 |
0,0,2,0 | 4 | 3 | 2 | 1 |
0,2 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 1 |
0,2,0 | 4 | 1 | 2 | 3 |
0,2,1 | 2 | 4 | 1 | 3 |
0,2,1,0 | 3 | 1 | 4 | 2 |
1 | 1 | 3 | 4 | 2 |
1,0 | 2 | 4 | 3 | 1 |
1,0,0 | 3 | 1 | 2 | 4 |
1,0,0,0 | 4 | 2 | 1 | 3 |
1,1 | 1 | 4 | 2 | 3 |
1,1,0 | 2 | 3 | 1 | 4 |
1,1,0,0 | 3 | 2 | 4 | 1 |
1,1,0,0,0 | 4 | 1 | 3 | 2 |
2 | 2 | 1 | 3 | 4 |
2,0 | 1 | 2 | 4 | 3 |
2,1 | 1 | 3 | 2 | 4 |
2,1,0 | 4 | 2 | 3 | 1 |
2,1,1 | 1 | 4 | 3 | 2 |
2,1,1,0 | 3 | 2 | 1 | 4 |
The next table shows the probability it will take 1 to 5 turns of the 24 possible ways to arrange the four price tags.
Turns Required
Turns | Number | Probability |
---|---|---|
1 | 1 | 4.17% |
2 | 4 | 16.67% |
3 | 8 | 33.33% |
4 | 9 | 37.50% |
5 | 2 | 8.33% |
Total | 24 | 100.00% |
Taking the dot product, the average number of turns needed, under this strategy, is 3.29167.
This question is asked and discussed in my forum at Wizard of Vegas.
Yes. It refers to a change in strategy for the second-player player if he has more than 2/3 the score of the first-place player.
Let's simplify the situation to a two-player game, as follows:
- Situation A: Second place has less than half of first place.
- Situation B: Second player has between 1/2 and 2/3 of first place.
- Situation C: Second place has more than 2/3 of first place.
Before going further, let me reminid the reader of a Jeopardy rule change pertaining to ties after Final Jeopardy. No longer do both players advance, but there is now a sudden death tiebreaker question. Here is such a situation.
Situation A
Let A=$10,000 and B=$4,000
Player A should not risk losing by betting no more than A-2B-1. If he doesn't feel confident in the category, he can bet $0. Either way, he ensures winning. In this case, A should bet between $0 and $1,999.
Player B has no hope, unless A bets too much and misses. Here, B should consider the score of third place and try to stay above him, if he can, winning $2,000 for second place, as opposed to $1,000 for third place.
Situation B
Let A=$10,000 and B=$6,000
The strategy for A is to expect B to bet everything and to bet enough to cover 2B if correct. However, to be safe, he shouldn't bet too much as to fall below B if incorrect. In this case, he should bet at least 2B-A+1 and A-B-1. In this case, the range is $2,001 and $3,999.
The strategy for B is to get at least enough to pass A if correct and up his entire score. In this case, $4,001 and $6,000.
If both players do as expected and follow this strategy, the only way player B can win is if A is wrong and B is right. The probability of this is about 19%.
Situation C
Here things get more complicated and involve more game theory and randomization.
Let A=$10,000 and B=$7,000.
Before going further, it is important to estimate the probability of the Final Jeopardy clue being answered correctly. Based on seasons 30 to 34, the first place player was correct 52% of the time and second place 46%. However, these probabilities are positively correlated. Here is a breakdown of all four possibilities:
- Both correct: 27%
- First place correct, second place incorrect: 25%
- First place incorrect, second place correct: 19%
- Both incorrect 29%.
Despite a Jeopardy average of 49% for the first two players, the probability of both being right or both being wrong is 56%.
Of course, these can change based on the category, but let's keep things simple and use the probabilities above.
In this situation, player B does not have to depend on A being wrong and B being correct. He can bet low, say $0, ensuring a win if A is wrong. In other words, if A bet enough to cover B, if correct, then he would risk falling below B if wrong and B bet $0.
However, if A predicted B would bet low, say $0, then A could lock in a win by also betting $0. Both player basically have a choice to make, to go low or high. A should wish to wager the same way as B and B should wish to wager the opposite way of B. If both players were perfect logicians, they would randomize their decisions.
In this case, a high bet by A should be 2B-A+1 to A-B-1, the same as for situation B. In this case $2,999 and $4,001. A low bet by A should be $0.
A high bet by B should be the same as for situation B, bet enough to pass A if correct. In this case, $3,001 and $7,000. A low bet by B should be $0.
Forgive me if I skip the math and get right to the randomization strategies for both players.
Player A should go high with probability 62.3% and low with probability 37.7%.
Player B should be high with probablity 61.2% and low with probability 38.8%.
Assuming both players following this randomization strategy and the probability pairings of being correct stated above, the probability of player A winning is 65.2%.
If player A had more than 2/3 the score of player B, his probability of winning would go up to 81.0%.
Both players should keep in mind the significance of the 2/3 rule when wagering on Double Jeopardy.